Lessons from Lobsters

04 September 2018

Last month, a truck carrying over four thousand lobsters slid off the road and turned over in the small town of Brunswick, Maine. The driver emerged from the crash relatively unscathed, but his crustacean cargo, which fell onto the road, had to be destroyed. Before the month was out, PETA (People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals) sent a proposal to the state government for a monument memorializing the slaughter. Shaped like a five-foot high granite tombstone, it would display a picture of a lobster and be inscribed with the words “In Memory of the Lobsters Who Suffered and Died at This Spot, August 2018, Try Vegan, PETA.” PETA Executive Vice President Tracy Reiman said “PETA hopes to pay tribute to these individuals who didn’t want to die with a memorial urging people to help prevent future suffering by keeping lobsters and all other animals off their plates.” The state Department of Transportation turned the proposal down.

Now, I work in Maine, and I can confidently assure you that Mainers don’t take kindly to proposals to keep lobsters off their plates. In this case, both locally and nationally, PETA came in for considerable ridicule. To many people, the notion of a lobster memorial seemed utterly absurd. But why should this be? Why should we cast aspersions on a memorial to the killing of 4500 lobsters, but take seriously a memorial to the wanton murder of 2980 human beings on September 11, 2001? That’s a serious philosophical question.

Press a person on it, and they’re likely to say something like “Because they’re only lobsters, and people’s lives matter a lot more than lobsters’ lives.” That’s an intuitively plausible, or at least understandable, response. I think it’s safe to say that, at a gut level, most of us consider humans’ lives far more significant than lobsters’ lives. But “intuition” is just a fancy, philosophical name for cognitive bias. So, appealing to intuition to justify a position is just appealing to bias to justify that position. That’s not to say that biases are without value, only that they’re not good enough all on their own. In this case, citing intuition boils down to something like “I just can’t help believing that human lives matter a lot more than lobster lives do.” And that doesn’t get us anywhere.

Notice that our imaginary interlocutor doesn’t say “Human lives matter more to me than the lives of lobsters do.” That would express a subjective moral stance. Instead, she states that human lives matter more than lobster lives do, which is a claim about the objective value of human lives in contrast to that of lobster lives.

Over the centuries, philosophers have tied themselves up in knots (an activity that we philosophers excel at) to rationally justify the intuition—the bias—that human lives matter more than the lives of the “lower” animals. Judging from the continuing disputes in moral philosophy, it’s safe to say that they haven’t succeeded.

Notice my use of the scare-quoted word lower in the last paragraph. That word provides the key to unpacking the idea that lobster lives don’t matter much, if at all, in the scheme of things. The notion that some forms of life are higher or lower than others strikes a chord in many of us, but when you begin think about it, it’s perplexing. It’s not an idea that comes from (or is endorsed by) biological science. In fact, one of the most important philosophical implications of Darwin’s theory was the demolition of the idea that some organisms rank higher than others.  

If we say that humans are higher than lobsters, we owe an explanation of in what sense they’re supposed to be higher. What’s at work here is what philosophers call the notion of intrinsic value. To get a hold of what’s meant by this, it’s useful to contrast intrinsic value with instrumental value. The instrumental value of a thing resides in its consequences—or, to put the point more crudely, in what it can get for you. Money is a good example. What’s the point of having money? Certainly not to just sit there and admire it, like one might do with Michelangelo’s David. The value of money is entirely instrumental. In contrast, the intrinsic value of a thing is its value in and of itself. For instance, some people think that happiness is intrinsically valuable. It’s not that we want to be happy because it leads to something else. We just want to be happy because…well… it’s good to be happy.

The people who think that PETA’s proposed lobster memorial is ridiculous are, I assume, happy to admit that lobsters have considerable instrumental value, as lobster fishing is a big part of Maine’s economy, but deny that lobsters have much if any intrinsic value.

The idea that some kinds of organisms are higher than others—in other words, the idea that the world of living things is organized as a hierarchy with those with the greatest intrinsic value at the top, those with the least value at the bottom, and everything else at one or another rank somewhere in-between—is known as the Great Chain of Being. For centuries, European scholars took for granted that the Great Chain provided the most accurate picture of the cosmos. Traditionally, God was placed at the apex of the hierarchy, because he is by definition the supremely perfect and infinitely valuable entity. And we Homo sapiens modestly placed ourselves not too far beneath him (“just below the angels”), because we suppose ourselves to have been fashioned in God’s image. In contrast, lobsters are relegated to quite a lowly rank in the pecking order, far below many other creatures. And that’s why they don’t count for much.

Where does the idea of the Great Chain of Being come from? According to the philosopher Arthur O. Lovejoy, the author of the immensely influential 1936 book The Great Chain of Being: A Study of the History of an Idea, it was cobbled together by philosophers in late antiquity, out of raw materials extracted from the writings of Plato and Aristotle. It persisted for centuries, and then faded out in the latter part of the eighteenth century as a scientific conception of species began to replace the older, prescientific one.  

Lovejoy’s book is an extraordinary work of scholarship—a brilliant contribution to the history of ideas. But his story of the career of the Great Chain of Being just can’t be right. Here’s why.

First, remember that I began this essay talking about reactions to PETA’s proposed roadside lobster memorial. If, as I’ve suggested, those who’ve ridiculed the idea—and the related idea that we shouldn’t eat animals—did so because they believe that lobsters are a lower form of life, that shows that, far from having faded away towards the end of the eighteenth century, the notion of the Great Chain of Being is alive and well at the beginning of the twenty-first.

Couldn’t this attitude be chalked up to scientific illiteracy? Nope. Scientists—in fact, professional biologists—also regularly indulge in this sort of hierarchical thinking. Biologists Emanuele Rigato and Alessandro Minelli demonstrated this in a survey of more than 67,000 articles in major biological journals, and guess what they found? The pre-Darwinian language of “higher” and “lower” infects lots of biological journals, even evolutionary ones (the distinguished journal Molecular Biology and Evolution is the worst offender, with 6.1% of the articles surveyed using hierarchical language).

The other reason why Lovejoy’s story has got to be wrong is that it’s too parochial. Even if the Great Chain of Being is just a philosophical artefact (which it isn’t), it’s not a uniquely Western one flowing from the thinking of Aristotle and Plato. In fact, if you abandon this assumption, and look around in other traditions, you’ll find its footprint all over the place. The hierarchical conception of nature makes an appearance in the book of genesis, where God empowers humans to lord it over the beasts of the field, as well as in Indian and West African cosmologies. One of the most striking examples is found among the Aztecs, who can hardly be accused of drawing on the sages of classical Athens. According to the anthropologist P. R. Sanday, “Gods, humans, and animals were ordered according to a chain of being in which each segment participated in a common essence and depended on other segments to survive…,” and so:

The present version of mankind was…placed below the gods and above all other animals in the ladder of power, merit, and perfection. This ladder was revealed in the eating order. Lower orders of animals ate one another and plants, animals at all of them, and the gods ate humans to subsist.

I’ve explained why Lovejoy’s story can’t be right. It doesn’t account for the staying power of hierarchical thinking in human psychology, or it’s persistence in science, or its wide distribution across cultures. But I haven’t shared my view of what the right explanation is, and why it is so easy to think that Lobster lives matter far less than human lives. That’s going to be the topic of next month’s blog.

 

 

 

Comments (5)


kauffball's picture

kauffball

Wednesday, September 5, 2018 -- 6:36 PM

I think the answer to this

I think the answer to this question is fairly simple, and it boils down to (see what I did there?) communication. People tend to order other animals in importance by how well we can communicate with them. This invariably means that we value human life first, then domesticated (pet) mammals, then wild mammals, then it gets a little murky. You'd think the next level would be domesticated farm mammals, but this isn't always the case because we have to put some cognitive distance between ourselves and that which we eat (I am not a vegetarian, this is not going to turn into a diatribe). But we always then structure vertebrates as higher than invertebrates. We may tell ourselves that this is due to cognitive ability, but science is showing this is not always the case. Crows may be better problem solvers than dogs, octopi may be smarter than cats. But we are poorly equipped to communicate with crows and octopi (we also cohabitate with them less), so we assume their cognitive abilities are poorer than cats and dogs. We know that lobsters communicate with each other primarily through chemical exchange (urinating on one another). If we allow lobsters have cognition and could peer into the lobster psyche they may assume that ants and other insects and arthropods that communicate primarily through chemical interaction have superior intellects to humans and mammals that just seem to roam around grunting, and we would be much lower on their hierarchical ordering.

Harold G. Neuman's picture

Harold G. Neuman

Thursday, September 6, 2018 -- 10:44 AM

What a waste of good lobster

What a waste of good lobster flesh. PETA does some good work. At times. Maybe someone should propose a new organization: PETP, People for the Ethical Treatment of People. Oh, I suppose we do not truly need a new group to champion the rights of homo sapiens, but on reflection, those bulwarks of defense we currently have do not necessarily deliver. Some of them have outlived their usefulness; others have forgotten what it was that spurred their evolution(s) in the first place. Let's reverse the roles for a moment, just for grins: what kinds of cognitive biases might lobsters have?

nonchalant's picture

nonchalant

Thursday, September 6, 2018 -- 6:23 PM

Maybe when we choose to

Maybe when we choose to justify the suffering of other species it's not just "intuition", but some sort of survival instinct? For example, dogs are also "lower" creatures, but people will be upset when a dog dies in a movie (in fact, many will be less upset when a human dies in a movie), and they will tell you that their dog is a equal member of a family entitled to all human benefits and more. I often hear that dogs are "better than people" and that we "do not deserve our dogs". But when PETA says "try vegan", people see it as an attack on their food supply, and their empathy is switching off. Lobsters do not deserve a memorial because lobsters are food, it's that simple. We are not mourning over our food. Your food is not your friend. Modern farms can be seen as concentration camps / mass killing sites. Atrocities are constantly being exposed, and it's probably just the tip of the iceberg. People are mostly aware of it, but they will ignore someone trying to point it out. It's out of debate for them because their life depends on these atrocious industries (or so they think). And not only that, they want these industries to achieve maximum economic efficiency and will ignore the implications. Regarding the "higher" and "lower" forms and their instrumental value, I guess the things will get more exciting when AI would become vastly superior to human intelligence and we will have a chance to see ourselves as less advanced/useful lifeform before we disappear or merge.

MJA's picture

MJA

Monday, September 10, 2018 -- 3:11 PM

The only thing missing in

The only thing missing in your essay Mr. Smith is equality.
Most of mankind has yet to reach the light at the end of the tunnel, the Promised Land, Dr. King's dream, where the measure of the measurer is equal and indivisible of all the rest. I can't promise to take you there either because we already are there, all we have to do is be it, be true.

God is just another name for One.
When all is equal all is One.
Be One
=

MJA's picture

MJA

Monday, September 10, 2018 -- 10:05 PM

I thought it important to add

I thought it important to add this: Where some might find the thought of unity or oneness spiritual, or religious, which it is, the proof was found scientifically, mathematically, philosophically, and empirically. Einstein's unified field equation, like truth, is much more simple than thought. =