Explanation at Its Best
Sep 30, 2019What makes an explanation a good explanation? Isn’t the simplest explanation always the best? Why do people often swallow crazy explanations? Those are just some of the questions we’re asking in this week’s episode about the nature of explanation.
Comments (11)
Harold G. Neuman
Sunday, September 8, 2019 -- 11:15 AM
In order to 'makeIn order to 'make explanations'; attain understandings; make judgments (as judges and hearing officers do); and generally assess the why(s); wherefore(s) and what-the-hell-really-happened of many scenarios, we use several primary kinds of algorithmic vehicles: adductive; inductive; and deductive reasoning. Adducing facts, as to the likelihood of one scenario being more probable than another, is certainly the least burdensome and among the 'simpler', 'elegant' means of arriving at a just (maybe) and equitable (ditto) outcome. Administrative law judges (I used to be one of those, although I was given the poor man's title: hearing officer) rely on background laws, policies and case law precedents, in order to-as simply and elegantly as possible-arrived at holdings on such matters. They don't ordinarily use the terms simple or elegant. Don't have to. They may be absolutely correct in their assessments of things, but may still have their decisions overturned at a higher level. Additionally, their original holding(s) may be restored at a still higher level of appeal (i.e., the court system itself). Induction and deduction are slightly different, but I won't go into that. Reduction is yet another means-but, it engenders controversy, as philosophers know full well. There are, then, different ways to skin the cat, and adductive arguments remain a gentleman's Damocles' Sword---Good luck with Ms. Lombrozo, guys!
Harold G. Neuman
Wednesday, September 18, 2019 -- 11:52 AM
In reading Wilfrid Sellars'In reading Wilfrid Sellars' SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS (Humanities Press, 1968), I came upon remarks concerning induction and law-like statements (section 7, page 118)., Beginning with: "In philosophy, one thing always leads to another, and it is tempting, at this point, to embark on an extended discussion of induction." He continues talking about 'law-like' statements; S-assertibility; semantics and so on. To conclude the paragraph-long section, he writes: ..."to understand the point of inductive reasoning one must understand the distinctive functions of matter-of-factual statements belonging to the level below that of law-like statements." So, it would seem that Sellars recognizes the need for a healthy command of language, when it comes to seeing how things hanging together form a (the?) foundation for effective, convincing communication. I personally have always found this helpful, because no matter who one's argument is directed to, an understandable vocabulary (whether written or spoken) is, as Sellars implies, the epitome of "Categorical Reasonableness".
Put more elegantly: an audience cannot grasp an explanation which is abstract; obscure or academically obfuscatory. Just sayin'...
(For those interested in the long version of Sellars' quip regarding philosophy helping us see how things hang together, see III of Chapter VI, section 19. on page 158 of this rather difficult book. That Sellars was an analytical philosopher is obvious. For anyone not up to the challenge, ignore this footnote.)
RepoMan05
Friday, October 4, 2019 -- 5:47 PM
The best explanations causeThe best explanations cause the reader or listener to actually learn something they either didnt know or ever considered; either in conjunction with something else they either knew or didn't or on its own. It's not whether or not your explanation was convincing. If your explanation was convincing or not is always seperate of its total possible value. You can teach far more than you're supposedly explaining and still have something valuable. What then does "best" mean?
Tim Smith
Tuesday, April 19, 2022 -- 3:58 AM
Sometimes a question answers.Sometimes a question answers. What is best? Why do you ask?
Daniel
Sunday, April 10, 2022 -- 9:06 AM
Is the "inference to the bestIs the "inference to the best explanation" describable also as the most preferable insufficient explanation? Take the so-called "crop circle" phenomenon in Wiltshire England. While some of them are explained unproblematically as to how they are produced, some apparently are not, and for these latter all available explanations seem equally insufficient. When however, some time ago, two farmers confessed to producing a few of them one night after leaving a tavern, the puzzle was thought by many to have been solved. Because of the high number of such designs and their complexity, however, the farmers' confession turned out to be just as faulty as all of the others, but continues to held by many as having settled the matter, presumably because it's grounded in actions which can be commonly understood. It's not the best explanation, therefore, but merely the most preferable. Instead of speaking of an "inference to the best explanation" among competing alternatives in discussions of informal logic, then, should we not instead rename it as an "inference to the preferable explanation" among equally bad ones?
Daniel
Sunday, April 10, 2022 -- 2:13 PM
Below is an interestingBelow is an interesting example from ontology which illustrates the point I'm trying to make above about optional veracity under negative epistemic conditions:
Key-- p: an impression of a tree produced by one's imagination but believed to be real, i.e. the hallucination of a tree;
q: a visual perception;
r: a real, existing tree.
If p then q
If q then either p or r (disjunction here is the exclusive use)
If r then q or not q
q
Therefore, p, --on account of a greater probability, since p is q all the time, and r only sometimes. But take the converse case:
If r then q or not q
If p then q
If p then not r
q
therefore, r, --since p must be q, but r is more likely to be.
Under the assumption that p and r are visually identical, two results are produced: r can never be a mere q, that is, if it's a real tree, it's not a mere visual impression; and p can only be a q, --if it's an hallucination, then that's all of it which actually exists. How q appears in the conclusion, either as a negation of r by self-affirmation in p, or an affirmation of r by self-negation of objective status as a mere impression, appears to be a matter of taste whose matter is optional, i.e. a preference.
Daniel
Friday, April 15, 2022 -- 8:55 AM
If the inference to the bestIf the inference to the best explanation is understood as a preference for one result among equally insufficient ones, then attempting to prove it and exclude the others by its demonstration would not only be useless, but indeed a bit rude. That doesn't imply however that there might not be a rule for which preferences are good ones. As an example of the application of such a rule, take the case where an empty bookshelf is abandoned on a side walk in a residential neighborhood, and two of its residents arrive at the same time to appropriate it. Neither one needs it, but both would like to have it in their possession. Assuming that both residents' preferences are conditioned by keeping it in one piece, what's the rule to which a potential adjudication can appeal? Would it not be with regard to how it will be used? If one has books and does a lot of reading and the other doesn't, then by the rule, the abandoned book case should go to the reader.
Kant's notion of a Deduction of a concept's claim of application to an object applies a similar rule. The term derives from the court system of the time and is designed for such cases as in the example above (Critique of Pure Reason, A84/B116). Kant's famous Transcendental Deduction is provided for general concepts of experience, or the "categories". He wants one because they're already used and trusted to both common sense and the science of his time. Without a Deduction showing it's not the case that there's no good reason for them, one use might be just as good as any other, generating a skepticism for the science of his day. The Deduction doesn't prove that the concepts apply to objects, only that they're best used that way.
A short account of Kant's argument is expressed below:
Key: a: apperception; a pure (unmixed with any prior experience) product of the productive imagination, consisting of everything one indirectly perceives prior to what one does perceive, or whatever in one's field of awareness one is not explicitly aware of; (synthetic aposteriori).
b: concepts of objects; (synthetic aposteriori).
c: categories of judgements; (analytic apriori).
1) b if and only if a
2) if a then not c
3) if c then b or not b
4) a,
5) therefore b,
6) therefore, if b then c. From two synthetic aposteriori premises you get an analytic apriori conclusion. The connection between the last two premises is not a valid one, but rather a condition arising from the definition of term a as conditioning any object of experience. If you have any objects at all, the categories have to already apply to them (B132-136).
A striking thing about the use of this argument is how Kant wants to therefore make the claim that all the categories analyzable from experience apply (A65/B89). If on the assumption of a unity of possible objects to which the categories apply one presupposes an unconditioned unity of these general concepts themselves, empirical knowledge is improved as a result, as shown by the progress in the physical sciences of his time. The transcendental Deduction in the first Critique is, then, an argument from Elegance: If it's true, it should improve the understanding, and if it improves the understanding, it must be true; which is a circle, but not a vicious one, since inductive results and imaginative form are reciprocally determined. The more one assumes the categories' analytic unity, the better the inductive results; and the better the inductive results, the stronger the grounds become for that assumption; which is similar to an argument from aesthetic response: If an object is beautiful on the surface, the more likely one judges correctly about what's underneath it; and the more what's underneath it is judged correctly, the more beautiful its surface becomes; (see also the Refutation of Idealism, B275-277). Kant's argument however doesn't do much better here of giving clear evidentiary or logical compulsion for his conclusion any more than the decision of whether a tree is an hallucination or not in the post of 4/10/22 above, but only that it's a generally preferable one for the understanding, or a matter of academic and, perhaps arguably to some degree aesthetic, preference.
Tim Smith
Tuesday, April 19, 2022 -- 2:52 AM
Explanation intrigues mostExplanation intrigues most often in where, when and how it is offered. Rarely do they answer why questions though the best do. Explanations stop at death or at the foot of craven belief.
I got a kick out of this show. Lombrozo is fantastic, as Josh is wont to say.
Daniel
Tuesday, April 19, 2022 -- 2:03 PM
So you're suggesting anSo you're suggesting an explanatory regress which ceases only with the failure of the researcher's biological system resulting in necrosis, or by a merely provisional reliability-component (third sentence above). The first suggestion is overly broad and easily refuted. To wit: why did the driver crash? --Because the automobile's braking system malfunctioned. The second claim however is to my mind a strong one and hangs upon the definition of "craven", which I've interpreted as "provisional". And that's the same as saying that no explanation is ever fully insulated from potential revision. Is this interpretation adequate to your meaning? If so, it indicates a radical epistemic coherentism whose presumed foundationalist opponents will want to clearly parse out the term "craven". Therefore, in deference to the naive Foundationalists, is it possible to grant them an elaborated account of what's meant by the term?
Tim Smith
Tuesday, April 26, 2022 -- 4:07 PM
Daniel,Daniel,
You are especially feisty of late.
Here is an explanation.
Pusillanimous.
The end.
Where, how and when.
Maybe Elon Musk will buy Philosophy Talk and add a thumbs up option, and save us from the naive foundationalists. My heart will likely stop before that happens. ;-)
In the meantime, I provisionally offer... pusillanimous.
DoubtEverything
Tuesday, November 29, 2022 -- 12:05 PM
Albert Einstein.. speakingAlbert Einstein.. speaking about..... "The religion of the future".... I remixed his quotes from throughout his life.. to make it flow more smoothly.
I enjoy making connections..
"I am a deeply religious nonbeliever - this is a somewhat new kind of religion."
"I have only two rules which I regard as principles of conduct. The first is: Have no rules. The second is: Be independent of the opinion of others."
Einstein said.. "Every one who is seriously involved in the pursuit of science becomes convinced that a Spirit is manifest in the laws of the Universe-a Spirit vastly superior to that of man, and one in the face of which we with our modest powers must feel humble."
"The more I study science, the more I believe in God."
"That deep emotional conviction of the presence of a Superior Reasoning Power, which is revealed in the incomprehensible universe, forms my idea of God."
"The more I learn of physics, the more I am drawn to metaphysics."
"Body and soul are not two different things, but only two different ways of perceiving the same thing. Similarly, physics and psychology are only different attempts to link our experiences together by way of systematic thought."
"Concerning matter, we have been all wrong. What we have called matter is energy, whose vibration has been so lowered as to be perceptible to the senses. There is no matter."
"I like to experience the universe as one harmonious whole. Every cell has life.
Matter, too, has life; it is energy solidified."
"Matter is spirit reduced to point of visibility." - "It is entirely possible that behind the perception of our senses, worlds are hidden of which we are unaware."
"Matter is Energy ... Energy is Light ... We are all Light Beings..
"We are slowed down sound and light waves, a walking bundle of frequencies tuned into the cosmos. We are souls dressed up in sacred biochemical garments and our bodies are the instruments through which our souls play their music."
The religion of the future will be a cosmic religion. It should transcend a personal God and avoid dogmas and theology. Covering both the natural and the spiritual, it should be based on a religious sense arising from the experience of all things, natural and spiritual, as a meaningful unity. Buddhism answers this description."
"I said before, the most beautiful and most profound religious emotion that we can experience is the sensation of the mystical. And this mysticality is the power of all true science. If there is any such concept as a God, it is a Subtle Spirit, not an image of a man that so many have fixed in their minds. In essence, my religion consists of a humble admiration for this Illimitable Superior Spirit that reveals itself in the slight details that we are able to perceive with our frail and feeble minds."
"To know that what is impenetrable to us really exists, manifesting itself as the highest wisdom and the most radiant beauty, which our dull faculties can comprehend only in their most primitive forms - this knowledge, this feeling, is at the center of TRUE religiousness. In this sense, and in this sense only, I belong to the rank of devoutly religious men."
"My religion consists of a humble admiration of the illimitable superior spirit who reveals himself in the slight details we are able to perceive with our frail and feeble mind. He who can no longer pause to wonder and stand rapt in awe, is as good as dead; his eyes are closed. The most beautiful thing we can experience is the mysterious. It is the source of all true art and science." - Albert Einstein
-