Are “Human” Embryos Human?

17 December 2020

This is my final essay in a series of three on the topic of abortion. In the earlier essays, I explained that some people think that referring to the unborn as “embryos” dehumanizes them, and just like the dehumanization of racial and ethnic minorities, this way of speaking is used to legitimate their murder. This analogy is mistaken. To dehumanize others is to think of them as dangerous animals or evil, monstrous beings. That’s not the case with embryos. Describing a being as an embryo is a far cry from considering it to be a creature akin to a cockroach or a beast or a monster.

Even so, opponents of abortion can still argue that if embryos belong to our species—which they obviously do—then they are human embryos, and they are therefore human beings. And if that’s right, they can argue that because killing innocent human beings is morally wrong, abortion is morally wrong.

I briefly explained in the previous installment why this argument doesn’t hold water. Now I want to dive deeper into why it doesn’t work and offer a diagnosis of what’s really at stake when people argue about the morality of abortion. This will open up basic questions about what it means to be human.

The problem with the pro-life argument that I sketched above is that being human and being a member of our species aren’t the same thing. Consider an alien from a distant planet that looks and behaves just like a member of our species. Is that alien human? You might answer, “No, of course not. She’s similar to a human, but she can’t be human, because she’s not a member of our species.” Or you might answer “Yes, the alien’s human. She’s just not an Earth human.” 

Both responses turn on the question of whether the being in question is a human being. In that way, it’s similar to the pro-life argument. But there are big problems with this way of thinking. First of all, “human” isn’t even a scientific category. “Homo sapiens is a scientific category, but “human” is a folk category. This means that the question of whether Homo sapiens are humans is a question about whether a scientific term (“Homo sapiens”) and a vernacular term (“human”) name the very same things. When identifying water with H2O, we’re saying that everything that people call “water” (when using the term correctly, according to the rules of their linguistic community), is what chemists call H2O. That identity can be confirmed by performing chemical analyses of samples of the stuff called “water.”  

But “human” is far more referentially promiscuous than “water” is. There are many examples of groups of people reserving the term “human” for themselves and describing other groups as non- or sub-human, and there are even cultures that include some other species in the category of the human. On top of all this, the scientists themselves don’t always equate humans with our species. Sometimes they characterize Neanderthals or other prehistoric hominids as humans too. So, it’s incorrect to say that “human” and “Homo sapiens” name the same beings. At best the relationship between the two terms is inexact, fluctuating, and contestable.

We’ve considered the question of the human taxonomically. Now let’s examine it developmentally. Some ways that we categorize living things only pertain to stages of their lives. For example, the American bullfrog (Lithobates catesbeianus) begins life as a fertilized egg, which hatches into a tadpole, which gradually becomes a frog. All of these developmental stages are stages of the same species, but only the final stage is properly characterized as a frog. Similarly, we can say that a fertilized ovum belongs to the species Homo sapiens but it only becomes human at a certain stage in its development. And just as there is no sharp boundary between the tadpole stage and the frog stage of the developmental trajectory of Lithobates catesbeianus, there is no definite point when Homo sapiens become human beings. So, even if all Homo sapiens can become human, it doesn’t follow that all Homo sapiens are human.

These reflections raise daunting questions about what it means to be human. The closer we look at the concept of the human, the more indefinite it appears.  

The search for some definite property—some fact of the matter—that makes an individual a human being looks more and more like a wild goose chase. Fortunately, we don’t have to conceive of humanness in this way. There is a much more realistic interpretation of what’s going on when we regard others as human beings, and it’s one that has the advantage of encompassing the multitude of ways that we deploy the concept of the human. 

To regard a being as human isn’t to recognize some fact about them. It’s to endow them a certain moral status. We don’t grant them that status because they are human. Rather, it’s our granting them that status that makes them human. Perhaps an analogy will help. When someone is knighted by the Queen of England, it’s not because they already possess the property of being a knight. When the Queen said to Elton John “I dub thee Sir Elton John…” she made him a knight by assigning him that status. 

Similarly, we make individuals human by assigning them a human status. That’s why the question of whether or not an embryo is a human being can’t be settled by facts about it. Strange as it may sound, it is neither true nor false to say that “human” embryos are human beings. It follows that the controversy over abortion isn’t really about the true nature of the unborn, even though it is often misconceived as such. It’s about whether to grant embryos the honorific title of “human” or to withhold it from them.

Image by Dr. Vilas Gayakwad on Wikimedia

Comments (11)


Matti Meikäläinen's picture

Matti Meikäläinen

Friday, December 18, 2020 -- 2:54 PM

I have not read your previous

I have not read your previous entries on this topic. And after completing this one I don’t think that’s likely. You might have shortened your essay up a bit by just saying ‘a human embryo is a human if me and my friends decide that it is.’ Or, as you finally put it: “It’s about whether to grant embryos the honorific title of “human” or to withhold it from them.” And what makes it that way and not the reverse? Shouldn’t that be where you put your argument?

At first, I wondered why you attempted to change the common understanding of “dehumanize.” You say, “To dehumanize others is to think of them as dangerous animals or evil, monstrous beings.” However the folks at Merriam-Webster (and others) say, ...“transitive verb: to deprive (someone or something) of human qualities, personality, or dignity.” Quite a difference, which you seem to allude to near the end of your short essay.

Dehumanization always seems to begin with a little tinkering with the language. Ask the women and minorities in your next class about that.

rabidtarsier's picture

rabidtarsier

Friday, December 18, 2020 -- 11:35 AM

I agree with your dissent of

I agree with your dissent of the redefinition of "dehumanize". But I would argue that for the word to be used meaningfully, it requires that what is being dehumanized was "human" to begin with. Calling a stapler a stapler is not dehumanizing it. It is merely failing to humanize it.

So whether speaking of embryos, people groups, dehumanizing is only meaningful if the parties are in agreement that something is human to begin with.

So let's say we agree that you are a human. If I call you a little rat, that's dehumanizing. But if you think of your pet hamster (I assume you don't really have a hamster, but who knows) as part of your family and call it your baby and confer to it human status, but I do not, I am dehumanizing your hamster from your perspective but not from mine. That makes it a useless term.

Matti Meikäläinen's picture

Matti Meikäläinen

Friday, December 18, 2020 -- 1:49 PM

By pointing out his feeble

By pointing out his feeble attempt to redefine “dehumanize” I was, perhaps too subtly, signaling that this author may be engaging in fallacious linguistic argumentation including equivocation. The heart of my criticism was that he needed to justify why he thinks we confer the moral status of human personhood on a fetus rather than take it away. And what moral argument supports doing so or not doing so. It’s really only a partial argument.

Matti Meikäläinen's picture

Matti Meikäläinen

Friday, December 18, 2020 -- 2:47 PM

Rabidtarsier,

Rabidtarsier,

I should have added; you say (and I assume David Livingstone Smith agrees) “So let's say we agree that you are a human.”

Is that the place one starts? If so, who is “we.” And what gives you and your cohorts this special power? Is that usually how a “rights” argument begins?

David Livingstone Smith's picture

David Livingsto...

Friday, December 18, 2020 -- 4:37 PM

"We" is one's community,

"We" is one's community, which legislates who is one of "us" and who is not. And yes, that strikes me as how rights arguments start.

Matti Meikäläinen's picture

Matti Meikäläinen

Saturday, December 19, 2020 -- 5:21 AM

Well, if that is what you

Well, if that is what you truly mean, then philosophy, especially ethics, becomes much easier. Justice becomes a simple matter of power politics. Justice and human rights are what Thrasymachus claimed, “...nothing else than the interest of the stronger.” So, actually it doesn’t matter if your opponents arguments are any good or not. They only need to be persuasive. By prevailing in politics one becomes, as you say, the “community which legislates who is one of us and who is not.” Thanks for the clarification.

Matti Meikäläinen's picture

Matti Meikäläinen

Sunday, December 20, 2020 -- 2:29 PM

After re-reading your essay,

After re-reading your essay, I think I may owe you an apology. My last rebuttal was intended as sarcastic. But, upon re-reading your essay, I think you may really mean what you appear to be saying. I think you may really intend to argue that because one cannot move from biological facts to moral worth, then whether one is a human being with moral worth is simply an arbitrary decision which we can choose to exercise at any point.

As you argue,“there is no definite point when Homo sapiens become human beings.” At this point in your analysis, it’s a mere discussion of facts—biological facts. That is, there is no logical point during biological growth where the mere biological facts attain moral worth. “So, even if all Homo sapiens can become human, it doesn’t follow that all Homo sapiens are human.” This is a shift in the use of language. Some would even claim it’s a linguistic fallacy in reasoning. But leaving that argument aside, the biological human grows up to become a biological adult whereupon he or she generally also becomes—poof!—a human with moral status. You, quite honestly in my opinion, conclude that “it’s our granting them that status that makes them human.” That is, a human being with moral worth and certain human rights. “[W]e make individuals human by assigning them a human status. … It’s about whether to grant embryos the honorific title of “human” or to withhold it from them.”

I’m not an advocate for the pro-life camp. But I do think whether one has moral worth is not an arbitrary matter. I refer back to my reference to Thrasymachus.

David Livingstone Smith's picture

David Livingsto...

Friday, December 18, 2020 -- 4:34 PM

Yes, I agree. But on my view

Yes, I agree. But on my view, simply calling someone a rat falls short of dehumanizing them. See my most recent book ON INHUMANITY: DEHUMANIZATION AND HOW TO RESIST IT (Oxford, 2020)

David Livingstone Smith's picture

David Livingsto...

Friday, December 18, 2020 -- 4:32 PM

Matti, there isn't a common

Matti, there isn't a common understanding of dehumanization. I have devoted the last 10 years of my life to the study of dehumanization. There are certainly varied conceptions of it, but blog series is focussed on my formulation of what dehumanization is, for reasons that are spelled out in the first of the series. For more detail, see my most recent book on this topic, ON INHUMANITY: DEHUMANIZATION AND HOW TO RESIST IT (Oxford, 2020)

Matti Meikäläinen's picture

Matti Meikäläinen

Sunday, December 20, 2020 -- 5:47 AM

If, as you say, there isn’t a

If, as you say, there isn’t a “common understanding of the concept of dehumanization” then I submit that pro-lifers are as free as you are to argue the ethical meaning of that concept. By the way, that’s exactly how language functions. In my opinion it is unfair argumentation to insist on your own definition of a concept as a way to debunk the position of your opponents.

Tim Smith's picture

Tim Smith

Saturday, December 19, 2020 -- 9:38 PM

Fair enough.

Fair enough.

I grant homo sapien embyos the rights and status of a human being. Just as I also grant the same right and status to the mother. Just as I also grant the right to the father's sperm. Just as I also grant the title human being to the rapist who provided that sperm.

I'm not sure where your argument clarifies here. Please help.

H2O can be snow. It can be a single molecule without the property of wetness. That single molecule will never be wet without relatively large and environmentally random concatenation of other H2O molecules. A tadpole is a frog in a very real sense of both words. That sense is the developmental context of proclaiming homo sapien embryos human. Left alone that embryo will die and decompose into mostly water molecules. H2O molecules on the other hand if left alone come together into something wet and at some point ironically become water.

Is Henrietta Lacks immortal? I think not. Is a homo sapien embryo a human. Yes. Is abortion right or wrong. Can I get a humane answer on that one?

Moral "human" status is not derived from our inhibition to commit violent acts. Morality is an appreciation of life, embryonic, maternal or even biastophilic.

Abortion should be legal up until one passes their preliminary examinations, and is positively justifiable up until one successfully defends their thesis. After that its all just murder.